[SOUND] All right. If enough of you are still watching this, then you know what that means. That means that in a matter of weeks, Walter is going to lose all of his hair. Now, Walter thinks he's going to have his head shaved. But, little does he know, that I am going to use this plucker, to pluck out one, by one, by one hair until he's bald. That's right. I'm going to pluck out his hair one at a time until he's bald. Bald, I tell you. Bald. [LAUGH] Yes, bald. [SOUND] Hello? Yes. Oh. Hey. Hey, yes. Were you watching, were you watching the Week 9 video just now? Yeah. Yeah, that's right. That's right. I was just announcing my plans for Walter. I was going to pluck out one hair at a time until he was bald. what do you mean that's impossible? How could that be impossible? Well, that's right, Walter is not bald now Well yeah, of course. You can't take something that isn't bald and make it bald by just pulling out one hair. That doesn't make any sense. So Wait. Does that mean that it's impossible for Walter to become bald by losing one hair at a time? Hang on. Let me write that down. Let me write that down. Don't go away. Okay? Let me think about this. Okay, so Walter is not bald. Well, that's true. Walter isn't bald right now. My whole point, is that I'm going to make him bald, by plucking out one hair at a time. Okay. But she says that you can't take something that's not bald and make it bald by just removing one hair. Okay, that's right, too. So, I can't make Walter bald by just plucking one hair out of his head. If I just pluck one hair out of his head, he's still going to be not bald. But then I'll pluck another hair out of his head. But, wait a second. If I pluck another hair out of his head, and he starts off being not bald, well then, even after I pluck another hair out of his head, he's still going to not be bald, because you can't take something that's not bald and make it bald by plucking just one hair. So even after I pluck two hairs out of Walters head, he'll still not be bald. Well, what if I pluck a third hair out of his head? Well, you can't take something that's not bald and make it bald by plucking one hair out of its head. So even after I pluck three hairs out of Walter's head, he'll still not be bald. Okay, but what if I do another hair? Well If he starts off being not bald, and I can't make him bald by just plucking one hair out of his head, then even after I pluck four hairs out of his head, he'll still not be bald. Now, wait a second. I could keep going like this. If it's true that you can't take a thing that's not bald and make it bald by plucking one hair out of it's head, then plucking Walter's hairs out one by one could never turn him from being not bald into being bald. Because there'd be no point where plucking one hair out of his head would turn him from being not bald into being bald. Okay. So this plan is not going to work. I know. I'm going to do five hairs at a time, instead of one hair at a time. Okay, let me get the big, let me get the big tweezers here and sharpen those up. [SOUND] Wait a second. If I do five hairs at a time, that means that I could get Walter to lose hair five times faster than if I do one hair at a time. But no matter how fast I get him to lose hair, I could never get him to lose more hair, five hairs at a time, than I could eventually get him to lose, by plucking out one hair at a time. I mean, however many hairs I can get him to lose pulling out five of his hairs at a time, I could still get him to lose the same number of hairs pulling out one hair at a time. So if it's true that a thing that's not bald can't become bald by losing one hair off it's head, then that means a thing that's not bald can't become bald by losing five hairs off it's head. Which means there's no way that Walter could become bald. You have just seen an example of what's called the paradox of vagueness. Let me explain to you what just happened. Consider this argument, that I was going through in the previous segment. Walter is not bald, there's premise one. That's obviously true. Right? Walter is not bald. Premise two, you can't turn something that's not bald into something that's bald by just removing a single hair. All right? Removing one hair is not going to make the difference, between something that's not bald and something that's bald. But the problem is that if both of those premises are true, then it follows, by mathematical deduction, that, no matter how many hairs Walter loses, he will not be bald. What do I mean by mathematical deduction? Well, an intuitive way of explaining it is this. Think about something that's not bald, like Walter. If premise two is true, then you can't turn that not bald thing into a bald thing by removing one hair. It's still going to not be bald. And so you can't turn that non-bald thing into a bald thing by removing one more hair. It's still going to not be bald. And you can't turn that non-bald thing into a bald thing by removing one, one more hair. It's still going to not be bald. And so on, for all the hairs it has. So, if these two premises are true, then it's gotta be true that no matter how many hairs Walter loses, he will not be bald. This argument is apparently valid. But here's the problem. If the argument is valid, then there's no possible way that premise one and premise two could both be true while the conclusion is false. You remember what a valid argument is. A valid argument is an argument where the premises can't all be true while the conclusion is false. But premise one is apparently true. You look at Walter, he's not bald. Premise two is apparently true. There's no occasion on which you could take something that's not bald, and turn it into something that's bald by removing a single hair. So premise two is apparently true. But the conclusion seems to be obviously false. It's ridiculous to say, no matter how many hairs Walter loses, he will not be bald. What if he lost all his hairs? So this conclusion seems absurd, and yet the argument seems valid. So this is why it's paradoxical. It's paradoxical because, any solution to this problem is going to be something that's contrary to appearances. Either premise one is false, and Walter really is bald, contrary to appearances. Or premise two is false and there really is some occasion on which you could take a non-bald thing and make it bald by removing a single hair. Or, the conclusion really is true, no matter how many hairs Walter loses, he will not be bald. That seems ridiculous. Or, alternatively, the argument isn't valid. And yet, as we saw, the argument seems plainly valid. So something is contrary to appearances here. And that's why this is a paradox, because no matter how we solve this, no matter whether we say premise one contrary to appearances, is false, or premise two, contrary to appearances, is false, or the conclusion, contrary to appearances, is true, or the argument, contrary to appearances, is invalid, no matter which of those things we say, what we're saying is something that's contrary to appearances. And so, that's why we call this a paradox. And why is it a paradox of vagueness? Here's why. The reason this paradox arises, is because the expression bald, doesn't have, a precise definition. Suppose I give a precise definition of bald. Suppose that I said, a person is bald, if they have exactly, 102, or fewer hairs on their head. Okay so I give a precise definition of bald. Well now that I've defined the word bald precisely, by specifying a precise number of hairs, or less, that a creature has to have on it's head in order to be bald, well, now that I've defined the word bald precisely, now, notice, premise two is obviously no longer true. You can take a non-bald thing and make it bald by just removing a single hair. An example of that is when you take a creature with 103 hairs on his head, and remove a single hair from those 103, well, now you've made it bald. Because now it has only 102 hairs, and according to our precise definition of bald, 102 hairs or fewer, that's bald. So, the reason the paradox arises is because bald is a vague expression. It doesn't have a precise definition. That's why this paradox arises. And to prove that to you, we could consider other examples of this same kind of paradox that use other vague expressions besides bald. For instance, suppose I take these letter magnets right here, and I start stacking them up, and adding one, by one, by one to the stack, in order to make a heap. Okay? Now, I'm trying to make a heap, or maybe I don't have a heap just yet. But I think, well if I keep adding them one, by one, by one, eventually I'll have a heap. Well, since heap is a vague term also, since there's no precise definition of heap, the problem is that you get the same kind of paradox with heap that you do with bald. Here, let me show you what I mean One magnet is not a heap. Right? You'll all agree with that. A single magnet by itself if not a heap of magnets. But, it seems, it seems that you can not take, you can not take a non-heap and turn it into a heap by adding a single magnet. All right? A single magnet is not going to make the difference between a non-heap and a heap. There's no definite point where you turn a non-heap into a heap by just adding one magnet. But again, if that's true, and the single magnet is not a heap, well, then two magnets will not be a heap. Right? Because you can't take a non-heap and turn it into a heap by adding a single magnet. And if two magnets is not a heap, and it's true that you can't turn a non-heap into a heap by adding a single magnets, a single magnet, then that means three magnets will not be a heap. And if three magnets is not a heap, and you can't turn a non-heap into a heap by adding a single magnet, then that means four magnets is not a heap. And we could continue this reasoning indefinitely. Which means that no amount of magnets makes a heap. So again, this argument appears to be valid by the reasoning I just went through. It seems that there's no way that both of the premises could be true while the conclusion's false. Premise one seems obviously true. One magnet is not a heap. Premise two seems obviously true, as well. You can't turn a non heap into a heap by just adding a single magnet. But the conclusion seems obviously false. If you have a billion magnets all stacked up, that's gotta make a heap. So, what's the problem here? If the argument is valid, then you can't have the premises all being true and the conclusion being false. And yet, the premises both seem true and the conclusion seems false. So what's the solution? Again, a paradox. Because no matter what we say about this, it's going to be something contrary to appearances, and once again, as in the previous case, the paradox arises because the expression heap is a vague expression. It has no precise definition. See, if we give a precise definition of heap, if we say that a heap is 102 things or more, then premise two is going to end up being false. You can turn a non-heap into a heap by adding just a single thing, namely, when you have 101 things and you just add one more thing to it. Then you've turned a non-heap into a heap. Because we've defined heap as precisely 102 things or more. Since the word, heap, in ordinary English, doesn't have a precise definition like that, premise two seems to be true. And since premise one seems to be true and the conclusion seems to be false, and yet the argument seems to be valid, we have a paradox. That's the paradox of vagueness.