1 00:00:02,660 --> 00:00:08,096 The next question has probably been bothering you ever since very early on in 2 00:00:08,096 --> 00:00:12,901 the previous lecture. Namely, if valid arguments can have false 3 00:00:12,901 --> 00:00:17,903 premises, then what good are they? Sure, there's this technical logician's 4 00:00:17,903 --> 00:00:22,905 notion of a valid argument, but why should we care whether arguments are 5 00:00:22,905 --> 00:00:25,892 valid if valid arguments can be really bad? 6 00:00:25,892 --> 00:00:30,963 Validity might be necessary for an argument to be good or at least for a 7 00:00:30,963 --> 00:00:35,965 deductive argument to be good because remember, there are also inductive 8 00:00:35,965 --> 00:00:40,195 arguments. But even though it's necessary, it's not 9 00:00:40,195 --> 00:00:43,335 enough. You can have a horrible argument but 10 00:00:43,335 --> 00:00:46,976 still valid. Well, the great thing about validity is 11 00:00:46,976 --> 00:00:52,329 that when you add true premises to a valid argument, then you get something 12 00:00:52,329 --> 00:00:56,897 that really is valuable, which we're going to call a sound argument. 13 00:00:56,897 --> 00:01:02,536 Because if you know that the premises are true and you also know that it's not 14 00:01:02,536 --> 00:01:06,962 possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion, false, 15 00:01:06,962 --> 00:01:10,340 then, you know, the conclusion must be true. 16 00:01:10,340 --> 00:01:14,323 So, in a sound argument, the conclusion has to be true. 17 00:01:14,323 --> 00:01:19,359 And that is what makes it valuable because if we can get a deductive 18 00:01:19,359 --> 00:01:23,193 argument to be sound, then you really got something. 19 00:01:23,193 --> 00:01:28,981 What you've got is a true conclusion. Officially then, a sound argument is one 20 00:01:28,981 --> 00:01:33,440 where the premises are true and the argument is valid. 21 00:01:33,440 --> 00:01:39,372 And we've got the same combinations of truth and falsity as possibilities that 22 00:01:39,372 --> 00:01:44,479 we had in valid arguments. You can have both premises and conclusion 23 00:01:44,479 --> 00:01:50,111 are true and then, if it's valid, the argument is sound and if it's not valid, 24 00:01:50,111 --> 00:01:53,941 it's not. Or you can have the premises are true and 25 00:01:53,941 --> 00:01:57,621 the conclusions false and then, it can't be valid. 26 00:01:57,621 --> 00:02:03,291 But if it's invalid, it's not sound. We can have the premises are false and 27 00:02:03,291 --> 00:02:08,047 the conclusions true. And then if it's valid, it's not sound 28 00:02:08,047 --> 00:02:13,973 and if it's invalid, it's not sound. Or we can have both the premises and the 29 00:02:13,973 --> 00:02:19,899 conclusion are false, and then, it's not going to be sound whether it's valid or 30 00:02:19,899 --> 00:02:23,252 not. So, the only combination, where it sound 31 00:02:23,252 --> 00:02:29,256 is when the premises are true and the argument is valid and, in that case, you 32 00:02:29,256 --> 00:02:33,828 know that the conclusion is true. What about lack of soundness? 33 00:02:33,828 --> 00:02:37,894 Well, there are two ways an argument yjay fail to be sound, namely, 34 00:02:37,894 --> 00:02:42,855 either the argument can be invalid or one of its premises can be false. 35 00:02:42,855 --> 00:02:46,370 So, it's a lot easier for an argument to be unsound. 36 00:02:46,370 --> 00:02:51,144 And we know that a deductive argument tries to be valid and, of course, it 37 00:02:51,144 --> 00:02:56,181 wants its premises to be true so a deductive argument is trying to be sound. 38 00:02:56,181 --> 00:02:59,910 And when it fails to be sound, it's not going to be any good. 39 00:02:59,910 --> 00:03:03,440 And the next question is how can you know? 40 00:03:03,440 --> 00:03:07,811 If you don't know whether the premises are true, you're not going to know 41 00:03:07,811 --> 00:03:11,933 whether the arguments sound. Well, not quite, because if you, if the 42 00:03:11,933 --> 00:03:16,930 argument's valid and you know it's valid, then you don't know whether it's sound 43 00:03:16,930 --> 00:03:21,739 unless you know the premises are true. But if you that the argument is invalid, 44 00:03:21,739 --> 00:03:26,298 you already know it's unsound, even if you don't know whether the premises are 45 00:03:26,298 --> 00:03:29,109 true. So, if you think about it, that shows why 46 00:03:29,109 --> 00:03:34,069 you want to be able to test for validity. Because if you can show the argument's 47 00:03:34,069 --> 00:03:38,746 invalid, then you're going to be able to, well, I know it's unsound, regardless of 48 00:03:38,746 --> 00:03:42,315 what you think about whether the premises are true or not. 49 00:03:42,315 --> 00:03:46,684 So, there's going to be some value to validity, namely, if you can show it's 50 00:03:46,684 --> 00:03:51,176 invalid, you're going to show it's unsound and that means that the deductive 51 00:03:51,176 --> 00:03:56,306 argument didn't get what it wanted. So, validity is going to be necessary for 52 00:03:56,306 --> 00:04:02,414 soundness and soundness is going to be important because it guarantees the truth 53 00:04:02,414 --> 00:04:08,210 of the conclusion, and then, validity derives its value from the fact that if 54 00:04:08,210 --> 00:04:11,175 it's not valid, it's not sound. Okay. 55 00:04:11,175 --> 00:04:13,760 Now, there's a more to say about validity. 56 00:04:13,760 --> 00:04:18,488 And we'll say a lot more about validity when we get to a formal logic in the 57 00:04:18,488 --> 00:04:22,587 second part of this course. But for now, we're just going to stick 58 00:04:22,587 --> 00:04:27,252 with this pretty intuitive notion of validity and see how we can use this 59 00:04:27,252 --> 00:04:30,027 notion of validity to reconstruct arguments.